Page 1 of 7
Journal #02 - January 2009
Boris Groys
Politics of Installation
The field of art is today frequently equated with the art market, and the artwork is primarily
identified as a commodity. That art functions in the context of the art market, and every work
of art is a commodity, is beyond doubt; yet art is also made and exhibited for those who do
not want to be art collectors, and it is in fact these people who constitute the majority of the
art public. The typical exhibition visitor rarely views the work on display as a commodity. At
the same time, the number of large-scale exhibitions—biennales, triennales, documentas,
manifestas—is constantly growing. In spite of the vast amounts of money and energy invested
in these exhibitions, they do not exist primarily for art buyers, but for the public—for an
anonymous visitor who will perhaps never buy an artwork. Likewise, art fairs, while
ostensibly existing to serve art buyers, are now increasingly transformed into public events,
attracting a population with little interest in buying art, or without the financial ability to do
so. The art system is thus on its way to becoming part of the very mass culture that it has for
so long sought to observe and analyze from a distance. Art is becoming a part of mass culture,
not as a source of individual works to be traded on the art market, but as an exhibition
practice, combined with architecture, design, and fashion—just as it was envisaged by the
pioneering minds of the avant-garde, by the artists of the Bauhaus, the Vkhutemas, and others
as early as the 1920s. Thus, contemporary art can be understood primarily as an exhibition
practice. This means, among other things, that it is becoming increasingly difficult today to
differentiate between two main figures of the contemporary art world: the artist and the
curator.
The traditional division of labor within the art system was clear. Artworks were to be
produced by artists and then selected and exhibited by curators. But, at least since Duchamp,
this division of labor has collapsed. Today, there is no longer any “ontological” difference
between making art and displaying art. In the context of contemporary art, to make art is to
show things as art. So the question arises: is it possible, and, if so, how is it possible to
differentiate between the role of the artist and that of the curator when there is no difference
between art’s production and exhibition? Now, I would argue that this distinction is still
possible. And I would like to do so by analyzing the difference between the standard
exhibition and the artistic installation. A conventional exhibition is conceived as an
accumulation of art objects placed next to one another in an exhibition space to be viewed in
succession. In this case, the exhibition space works as an extension of neutral, public urban
space—as something like a side alley into which the passerby may turn upon payment of an
admission fee. The movement of a visitor through the exhibition space remains similar to that
of someone walking down a street and observing the architecture of the houses left and right.
It is by no means accidental that Walter Benjamin constructed his “Arcades Project” around
this analogy between an urban stroller and an exhibition visitor. The body of the viewer in this
setting remains outside of the art: art takes place in front of the viewer’s eyes—as an art
object, a performance, or a film. Accordingly, the exhibition space is understood here to be an
empty, neutral, public space—a symbolic property of the public. The only function of such a
space is to make the art objects that are placed within it easily accessible to the gaze of the
visitors.
Page 2 of 7
The curator administers this exhibition space in the name of the public—as a representative of
the public. Accordingly, the curator’s role is to safeguard its public character, while bringing
the individual artworks into this public space, making them accessible to the public,
publicizing them. It is obvious that an individual artwork cannot assert its presence by itself,
forcing the viewer to take a look at it. It lacks the vitality, energy, and health to do so. In its
origin, it seems, the work of art is sick, helpless; in order to see it, viewers must be brought to
it as visitors are brought to a bed-ridden patient by hospital staff. It is no coincidence that the
word “curator” is etymologically related to “cure”: to curate is to cure. Curating cures the
powerlessness of the image, its inability to show itself by itself. Exhibition practice is thus the
cure that heals the originally ailing image, that gives it presence, visibility; it brings it to the
public view and turns it into the object of the public’s judgment. However, one can say that
curating functions as a supplement, like a pharmakon in the Derridean sense: it both cures the
image and further contributes to its illness.1 The iconoclastic potential of curation was
initially applied to the sacral objects of the past, presenting them as mere art objects in the
neutral, empty exhibition spaces of the modern museum or Kunsthalle. It is curators, in fact,
including museum curators, who originally produced art in the modern sense of the word. The
first art museums—founded in the late 18th and early 19th centuries and expanded in the
course of the 19th century due to imperial conquests and the pillaging of non-European
cultures—collected all sorts of “beautiful” functional objects previously used for religious
rites, interior decoration, or manifestations of personal wealth, and exhibited them as works of
art, that is, as defunctionalized autonomous objects set up for the mere purpose of being
viewed. All art originates as design, be it religious design or the design of power. In the
modern period as well, design precedes art. Looking for modern art in today’s museums, one
must realize that what is to be seen there as art is, above all, defunctionalized design
fragments, be it mass-cultural design, from Duchamp’s urinal to Warhol’s Brillo Boxes, or
utopian design that—from Jugendstil to Bauhaus, from the Russian avant-garde to Donald
Judd—sought to give shape to the “new life” of the future. Art is design that has become
dysfunctional because the society that provided the basis for it suffered a historical collapse,
like the Inca Empire or Soviet Russia.
In the course of the Modern era, however, artists began to assert the autonomy of their
art—understood as autonomy from public opinion and public taste. Artists have required the
right to make sovereign decisions regarding the content and the form of their work beyond
any explanation or justification vis-à- vis the public. And they were given this right—but only
to a certain degree. The freedom to create art according to one’s own sovereign will does not
guarantee that an artist’s work will also be exhibited in the public space. The inclusion of any
artwork in a public exhibition must be—at least potentially—publicly explained and justified.
Though artist, curator, and art critic are free to argue for or against the inclusion of some
artworks, every such explanation and justification undermines the autonomous, sovereign
character of artistic freedom that Modernist art aspired to win; every discourse legitimizing an
artwork, its inclusion in a public exhibition as only one among many in the same public space,
can be seen as an insult to that artwork. This is why the curator is considered to be someone
who keeps coming between the artwork and the viewer, disempowering the artist and the
viewer alike. Hence the art market appears to be more favorable than the museum or
Kunsthalle to Modern, autonomous art. In the art market, works of art circulate singularized,
decontextualized, uncurated, which apparently offers them the opportunity to demonstrate
their sovereign origin without mediation. The art market functions according to the rules of
the Potlatch as they were described by Marcel Mauss and by Georges Bataille. The sovereign
decision of the artist to make an artwork beyond any justification is trumped by the sovereign
Page 3 of 7
decision of a private buyer to pay for this artwork an amount of money beyond any
comprehension.
Now, the artistic installation does not circulate. Rather, it installs everything that usually
circulates in our civilization: objects, texts, films, etc. At the same time, it changes in a very
radical way the role and the function of the exhibition space. The installation operates by
means of a symbolic privatization of the public space of an exhibition. It may appear to be a
standard, curated exhibition, but its space is designed according to the sovereign will of an
individual artist who is not supposed to publicly justify the selection of the included objects,
or the organization of the installation space as a whole. The installation is frequently denied
the status of a specific art form, because it is not obvious what the medium of an installation
actually is. Traditional art media are all defined by a specific material support: canvas, stone,
or film. The material support of the installation medium is the space itself. That does not
mean, however, that the installation is somehow “immaterial.” On the contrary, the
installation is material par excellence, since it is spatial—and being in the space is the most
general definition of being material. The installation transforms the empty, neutral, public
space into an individual artwork—and it invites the visitor to experience this space as the
holistic, totalizing space of an artwork. Anything included in such a space becomes a part of
the artwork simply because it is placed inside this space. The distinction between art object
and simple object becomes insignificant here. Instead, what becomes crucial is the distinction
between a marked, installation space and unmarked, public space. When Marcel Broodthaers
presented his installation Musée d’Art Moderne, Département des Aigles at the Düsseldorf
Kunsthalle in 1970, he put up a sign next to each exhibit saying: “This is not a work of art.”
As a whole, however, his installation has been considered to be a work of art, and not without
reason. The installation demonstrates a certain selection, a certain chain of choices, a logic of
inclusions and exclusions. Here, one can see an analogy to a curated exhibition. But that is
precisely the point: here, the selection and the mode of representation is the sovereign
prerogative of the artist alone. It is based exclusively on personal sovereign decisions that are
not in need of any further explanation or justification. The artistic installation is a way to
expand the domain of the sovereign rights of the artist from the individual art object to that of
the exhibition space itself.
This means that the artistic installation is a space in which the difference between the
sovereign freedom of the artist and the institutional freedom of the curator becomes
immediately visible. The regime under which art operates in our contemporary Western
culture is generally understood to be one that grants freedom to art. But art’s freedom means
different things to a curator and to an artist. As I have mentioned, the curator—including the
so-called independent curator—ultimately chooses in the name of the democratic public.
Actually, in order to be responsible toward the public, a curator does not need to be part of
any fixed institution: he or she is already an institution by definition. Accordingly, the curator
has an obligation to publicly justify his or her choices—and it can happen that the curator fails
to do so. Of course, the curator is supposed to have the freedom to present his or her argument
to the public—but this freedom of the public discussion has nothing to do with the freedom of
art, understood as the freedom to make private, individual, subjective, sovereign artistic
decisions beyond any argumentation, explanation, or justification. Under the regime of artistic
freedom, every artist has a sovereign right to make art exclusively according to private
imagination. The sovereign decision to make art in this or that way is generally accepted by
Western liberal society as a sufficient reason for assuming an artist’s practice to be legitimate.
Of course, an artwork can also be criticized and rejected—but it can only be rejected as a
whole. It makes no sense to criticize any particular choices, inclusions, or exclusions made by